Karl Marx

Error message

  • Deprecated function: The each() function is deprecated. This message will be suppressed on further calls in _menu_load_objects() (line 579 of /var/www/drupal-7.x/includes/menu.inc).
  • Notice: Trying to access array offset on value of type int in element_children() (line 6600 of /var/www/drupal-7.x/includes/common.inc).
  • Notice: Trying to access array offset on value of type int in element_children() (line 6600 of /var/www/drupal-7.x/includes/common.inc).
  • Notice: Trying to access array offset on value of type int in element_children() (line 6600 of /var/www/drupal-7.x/includes/common.inc).
  • Notice: Trying to access array offset on value of type int in element_children() (line 6600 of /var/www/drupal-7.x/includes/common.inc).
  • Notice: Trying to access array offset on value of type int in element_children() (line 6600 of /var/www/drupal-7.x/includes/common.inc).
  • Notice: Trying to access array offset on value of type int in element_children() (line 6600 of /var/www/drupal-7.x/includes/common.inc).
  • Notice: Trying to access array offset on value of type int in element_children() (line 6600 of /var/www/drupal-7.x/includes/common.inc).
  • Notice: Trying to access array offset on value of type int in element_children() (line 6600 of /var/www/drupal-7.x/includes/common.inc).
  • Notice: Trying to access array offset on value of type int in element_children() (line 6600 of /var/www/drupal-7.x/includes/common.inc).
  • Notice: Trying to access array offset on value of type int in element_children() (line 6600 of /var/www/drupal-7.x/includes/common.inc).
  • Notice: Trying to access array offset on value of type int in element_children() (line 6600 of /var/www/drupal-7.x/includes/common.inc).
  • Notice: Trying to access array offset on value of type int in element_children() (line 6600 of /var/www/drupal-7.x/includes/common.inc).
  • Notice: Trying to access array offset on value of type int in element_children() (line 6600 of /var/www/drupal-7.x/includes/common.inc).
  • Notice: Trying to access array offset on value of type int in element_children() (line 6600 of /var/www/drupal-7.x/includes/common.inc).
  • Notice: Trying to access array offset on value of type int in element_children() (line 6600 of /var/www/drupal-7.x/includes/common.inc).
  • Notice: Trying to access array offset on value of type int in element_children() (line 6600 of /var/www/drupal-7.x/includes/common.inc).
  • Notice: Trying to access array offset on value of type int in element_children() (line 6600 of /var/www/drupal-7.x/includes/common.inc).
  • Notice: Trying to access array offset on value of type int in element_children() (line 6600 of /var/www/drupal-7.x/includes/common.inc).
  • Notice: Trying to access array offset on value of type int in element_children() (line 6600 of /var/www/drupal-7.x/includes/common.inc).
  • Notice: Trying to access array offset on value of type int in element_children() (line 6600 of /var/www/drupal-7.x/includes/common.inc).
  • Notice: Trying to access array offset on value of type int in element_children() (line 6600 of /var/www/drupal-7.x/includes/common.inc).
  • Notice: Trying to access array offset on value of type int in element_children() (line 6600 of /var/www/drupal-7.x/includes/common.inc).
  • Notice: Trying to access array offset on value of type int in element_children() (line 6600 of /var/www/drupal-7.x/includes/common.inc).
  • Notice: Trying to access array offset on value of type int in element_children() (line 6600 of /var/www/drupal-7.x/includes/common.inc).
  • Notice: Trying to access array offset on value of type int in element_children() (line 6600 of /var/www/drupal-7.x/includes/common.inc).
  • Notice: Trying to access array offset on value of type int in element_children() (line 6600 of /var/www/drupal-7.x/includes/common.inc).
  • Notice: Trying to access array offset on value of type int in element_children() (line 6600 of /var/www/drupal-7.x/includes/common.inc).
  • Notice: Trying to access array offset on value of type int in element_children() (line 6600 of /var/www/drupal-7.x/includes/common.inc).
  • Notice: Trying to access array offset on value of type int in element_children() (line 6600 of /var/www/drupal-7.x/includes/common.inc).
  • Notice: Trying to access array offset on value of type int in element_children() (line 6600 of /var/www/drupal-7.x/includes/common.inc).
  • Notice: Trying to access array offset on value of type int in element_children() (line 6600 of /var/www/drupal-7.x/includes/common.inc).
  • Notice: Trying to access array offset on value of type int in element_children() (line 6600 of /var/www/drupal-7.x/includes/common.inc).
  • Notice: Trying to access array offset on value of type int in element_children() (line 6600 of /var/www/drupal-7.x/includes/common.inc).
  • Notice: Trying to access array offset on value of type int in element_children() (line 6600 of /var/www/drupal-7.x/includes/common.inc).
  • Notice: Trying to access array offset on value of type int in element_children() (line 6600 of /var/www/drupal-7.x/includes/common.inc).
  • Notice: Trying to access array offset on value of type int in element_children() (line 6600 of /var/www/drupal-7.x/includes/common.inc).
  • Notice: Trying to access array offset on value of type int in element_children() (line 6600 of /var/www/drupal-7.x/includes/common.inc).
  • Notice: Trying to access array offset on value of type int in element_children() (line 6600 of /var/www/drupal-7.x/includes/common.inc).
  • Notice: Trying to access array offset on value of type int in element_children() (line 6600 of /var/www/drupal-7.x/includes/common.inc).
  • Notice: Trying to access array offset on value of type int in element_children() (line 6600 of /var/www/drupal-7.x/includes/common.inc).
  • Notice: Trying to access array offset on value of type int in element_children() (line 6600 of /var/www/drupal-7.x/includes/common.inc).
  • Notice: Trying to access array offset on value of type int in element_children() (line 6600 of /var/www/drupal-7.x/includes/common.inc).
  • Notice: Trying to access array offset on value of type int in element_children() (line 6600 of /var/www/drupal-7.x/includes/common.inc).
  • Notice: Trying to access array offset on value of type int in element_children() (line 6600 of /var/www/drupal-7.x/includes/common.inc).
  • Notice: Trying to access array offset on value of type int in element_children() (line 6600 of /var/www/drupal-7.x/includes/common.inc).
  • Notice: Trying to access array offset on value of type int in element_children() (line 6600 of /var/www/drupal-7.x/includes/common.inc).
  • Deprecated function: implode(): Passing glue string after array is deprecated. Swap the parameters in drupal_get_feeds() (line 394 of /var/www/drupal-7.x/includes/common.inc).

Value Par Excellence: Money versus Real Values

Published by Anonymous (not verified) on Tue, 23/04/2024 - 6:00am in

Tags 

Karl Marx, money

The Past & Present Reading Group is discussing, in the first half of 2024, Karl Marx’s Grundrisse: Foundations of the Critique of Political Economy (Rough Draft) written during 1857–1858. This work is often considered a crucial read to grasp Marx’s methods of analysis, with Marx diving off Hegel as one might a springboard. Yet our group has immediately plunged into deep swirling waters of postcapitalist debates over money. This is hardly surprising given that Notebook I of Grundrisse centres on money.

Money and Marx

In his ‘Chapter on Money’, Marx critiques certain thinking on money by economists and the positioning of money by his political opponents in radical socialist transformation. He draws on ideas from both of the two main trains of monetary thought, a commodity theory of money and a credit theory of money. We see glimpses of his developing what will become a unique theory of the money commodity and links to earlier work characterised as an alienation theory of money (Nelson 1999).

In the Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844 Marx pointed out that ‘the extension of products and needs becomes a contriving and ever-calculating subservience to inhuman, sophisticated, unnatural and imaginary appetites’. Moreover, money and prices resulted in a ‘distorting and confounding of all human and natural qualities, the fraternisation of impossibilities’. But it is even more sinister – ‘the divine power of money – lies in its character as men’s estranged, alienating and self-disposing species-nature’ so that ‘[m]oney is the alienated ability of mankind’. (Italics as in the source.)

Opposing familiar interpretations of Marx’s vision and theories of change that sweep aside money and circulation as if secondary to production, we read in Grundrisse that ‘the money relation is itself a relation of production if production is looked at in its totality’ (Marx, 1993: 214). Moreover, withdrawn from circulation ‘accumulated to form a treasure … as a result of circulation’, money ‘closes the circle with itself’. In other words, consolidated as a measure, medium and potential investment, ‘[t]his aspect [of money] already latently contains its quality as capital’ (Marx, 1993: 216). Money defines capital: capital is money making more money. Once money exists, payment of labour is not only possible but also probable. Money is the connective tissue, language, and unit of calculations driving the everyday productive practices of capitalists in their production for trade.

In Grundrisse, Marx even seems to position himself as what has become known as a ‘nonmarket socialist’ –  socialism is impossible without attending to abolishing class, state, market, waged labour and money immediately in the transformational process:

Strike out money, and one would thereby either be thrown back to a lower stage of production (corresponding to that of auxiliary barter), or one would proceed to a higher stage, in which exchange value would no longer be the principal aspect of the commodity, because social labour, whose representative it is, would no longer appear merely as socially mediated private labour. (Marx, 1993: 214)

This line of thought was never lost. A year before Marx died, in their ‘Preface to the 1882 Russian edition’ of the Communist Manifesto (reprinted in Miéville, 2022: 239), he and Engels speculated whether ‘the present Russian common ownership of land may serve as the starting point for a communist development’. After all ‘more than half the land [was] owned in common by the peasants’ there while in North America small and middle-sized famers were being out-competed by ‘giant farms’ alongside ‘a mass industrial proletariat and a fabulous concentration of capital funds’.

Marx held money in contempt as the seed and regenerative tool of capital, and sought transformation to realise a world resplendent in real, social and ecological values. Such values reverberate through his work and provide the material of his standpoint against money. Money, which is at one and the same time ‘the existing and active concept of value’ and ‘the general confounding and confusing of all things – the world upside down – the confounding and confusing of all natural and human qualities’. In contrast, socialism ‘proceeds from the theoretically and practically sensuous consciousness of man and of nature as the essence’ and realises ‘a new manifestation of the forces of human nature and a new enrichment of human nature’. (Italics as in the source.)

A postcapitalism beyond money

Marx’s work inspired and reinforced my thinking on postcapitalism without money. A value-based abolition | revolution in which real values are the essential bases of both postcapitalist transformative strategies and end-point visions has become an enduring focus of mine. Notable among associated works is a doctoral study on Marx’s concept of money, resulting in Marx’s Concept of Money: The God of Commodities (1999/2014) and Life Without Money: Building Fair and Sustainable Economies, a non-market socialist collection published in 2011 that I co-edited (with Frans Timmerman). The latter is akin to a twenty-first century sequel to Non-Market Socialism in the Nineteenth and Twentieth Century (1987) edited by Maximilien Rubel and John Crump. Capitalism Nature Socialism published my article ‘“Your money or your life”: Money and socialist transformation’ (2016), subsequently shortlisted for the 2017 AIPEN Richard Higgot Journal Article Prize.

What’s wrong with money? Isn’t production for trade with market exchange more efficient and effective than any other system? Such questions need framing in the here and now of burgeoning socio-political inequities and apocalyptic ecological unsustainabilities. Global to local consumption patterns vary widely so we need to transform our practices to enable us all to live within one-planet footprints while satisfying our basic needs, neither more nor less. The needy must increase consumption to get ‘enough’ while others must significantly cut consumption and change their life styles radically to just consume ‘enough.’ No novel technologies or practical discoveries are necessary but the capitalist system (indeed any market-based system) is inadequate and inappropriate to this task. Why is this so?

Prices, monetary exchange and monetary relations evolve in an anthropocentric game that we play every day. Rather than alleviate inequity, monetary dynamics and relations engender and reproduce inequities. Practically everyone’s security relies on their monetary income or worth. Monetary exchange is all about gain and loss. We live in a world of privatised, competitive and secret production for trade, where monetary incomes – whether wages, welfare payments, dividends from shares and securities, or guaranteed minimum incomes – do not necessarily facilitate the satisfaction of the real needs of diverse householders. Market-based production does not plan or aim to produce for all people’s needs in either qualitative or quantitative ways. Prices do not, and cannot, embody the costs of ecological regeneration to conserve and preserve the needs of Earth (nature).

In short, production for trade does not and cannot satisfy either people’s or Earth’s needs. So, what kind of system might? In designing transformational strategies we need clear visions. I have applied ecosocialist, postcapitalist, ecofeminist and degrowth perspectives on nonmarket socialism in Beyond Money: A Postcapitalist Strategy (2022). An eight-minute video made for educational and activist screenings, Beyond Money: Yenomon (2022), is based on Chapter 3 of the book. It briefly sketches a nonprescriptive grassroots equivalent-free imaginary designed to give content to discussions of a postcapitalist nonmonetary economy that many find difficult to visualise. This is a world based on real values, social and ecological values, where local to global (glocal) co-governance replaces money as the organising principle of a society.

A glocal model of collective sufficiency

In this glocal model neither autonomy nor local collective sufficiency equal autarky. Relationships within a world of locally collectively sufficient cells would be as interdependent and independent as cells of a body. Organic and grassroots – rather than market-based, hierarchical or bureaucratic organisation – enables efficiency and effectiveness. The imaginary is of a global network of collectively sufficient, cell-like communities each responsible for the sustainability of the local environs off which they benefit in order to live. Such communities would have variable settlement patterns and sizes appropriate to each sub-sub-bioregion capable of sustaining them.

Direct and local satisfaction of essentials is ecologically and socially efficient. Of course certain needs are only satisfied by collaborating with people outside the neighbourhood community. Each cell intentionally and accidentally develops surpluses to share with other communities. Interrelationships coordinating the storage and transfers of such would occur continuously. In short, every community would be relatively autonomous and seamlessly networked globally. Universal principals of satisfying Earth’s and people’s needs would be shared, so production and exchange is more organic, complex and flexible. Cogovernors would accept and deal in customising ways with incomparable ecological and social values, contingencies and circumstances that prices and monetary calculations disavow.

There is no private property, no public property; the entire Earth is commons with clear and universal principles for commoning, sharing land, waters and so on. Secure and fair use-rights oblige users to respect and support the regeneration of Earth as well as humanity. Using horizontalist forms of governance – such as assemblies and accountable working parties from sub-community through to global spheres – communities decide what they need to grow, do and make to ensure that the needs of all residents and local ecosystems are met.

Responsibilities for numerous and various ecological and social aspects are delegated to criss-crossing and interrelating nodes, meaning that networks of power are decentralised and highly distributed. The working group responsible for a mountain range is different from the working group/s associated with co-governance of the water supplies in an associated catchment. Communities form joint approaches to similar or common challenges and share responsibilities and outputs from conjoined nodes of production. They share knowledge, skills and productive responsibilities within their ecological locale, but maintain strong concerns, relations and interactions with those beyond, especially neighbouring communities. Patents and intellectual property do not exist. A globally shared open access internet enables sharing of ideas, designs, techniques, and technologies and organisational innovations. Most education and training occurs on the job with peer support.

Everyone contributes time to collective production and, in return, has their basic needs met. Every household guesstimates their basic needs for one year. Working groups report on the ecological capacity of the local area and capability of locals to fulfil these various needs. Plans are revised and adjusted. All community members plan how to create and care for things and decide who gets what in assemblies and other horizontally organised processes. All year round, they work and monitor and tweak how to fulfil these orders, reporting back to the community at assemblies and through other processes to revise as necessary.

Once established, planning for everyone’s basic needs incorporates past and experiential knowledge of local area and cultural preferences. Producing food, providing health and energy services, clothing and housing, water and so on for particular, already specified, people means production for demand. Money or markets are unnecessary, superfluous. Every service or thing created goes to those who ordered them.

At the same time, community members discuss and negotiate ‘compacts’ to produce for and to receive from neighbouring (or more distant) communities those goods and services that they cannot find or make locally. In these ways they prevent overconsumption, scarcity and waste. Things that are not needed by certain residents are passed onto others to use, to repair, to reconstitute or recycle. Collective stores for emergencies can also fill unforeseen gaps. Goods and active contributions are shared with neighbouring and further flung communities. Production for markets and money is replaced by local decision-making, direct production for demand and distributed on the basis of need.

In all these ways decision-making focuses on diverse real, biophysical, ecological and social measures and values – ‘real values’. Such values, qualities and characteristics go far beyond simple use-values related to the needs of consumers and users. By way of an example, trees would be understood in ways much more akin to the practices and perspectives of ecologically alert Indigenous people, each and every type, size and age of a tree being seen as the source and beneficiary of multiple qualities of its surrounds full of ecological beings and relationships.

If a tree bears fruit, such as apples, they can be quantified by number or weight and such quantities might be comparable with certain other fruit, such as pears in terms of their contribution to the community’s and local environment’s well-being. But an apple has so many other potential qualities for humans and Earth. Such qualities must be weighed, quantified and balanced appropriately and differentially. No false and simplistic general equivalent – such as money in prices reflecting supply and demand (among other factors), or time chits (associated with labour time) or energy equivalence – can compare the incomparable complex of values that every single thing or service means in context. Experienced people who directly interact with their environs are capable of such evaluations.

This sketch of a community mode of production draws from Chapter 3 in Beyond Money. In this model the reward for contributing to collective daily tasks is lifelong security of communally meeting not only all people’s but also Earth’s basic needs. Real, social and ecological, values offer the democratic and materialist terms and perspectives for replacing money as the organising principle of society. Co-governance is practised in horizontal direct ways on the basis of subsidiarity as such power is highly distributed and continuously held in check through accountability and rotating roles. I see this in Marxian terms as offering a context within which people can fulfil their real human potential as creative, active beings freely and powerfully, living convivially with other humans and the more-than-human world.

Strategic issues

Further questions for activists and researchers cluster around strategic issues of how to get there. Chapters in Beyond Money show how the women’s movement, diverse environmental movements and certain Indigenous movements have applied and critiqued money and argue why and how they would benefit from taking explicit anti-money and post-monetary stances. There are similar treatments with respect to degrowth (Exner et al, 2020; Nelson, 2024). Here we argue that emancipatory movements advocating for justice, democratic power, and ecological sustainability will keep treading water or losing ground unless they advocate abolishing the monetary-cum-market system so that they can exclusively promote real social and ecological values in their demands and solutions.

Abolition | revolution approaches not only deny capitalists their material and ideological power but also accept that an economy based on markets is irrational in both social and ecological terms because it is not, and cannot be, designed to address real needs of all humans and Earth. Difficulties with seeing money in fatal terms at the heart of an irrational system as outlined by Marx in Grundrisse – for instance in his critiques of money substitutes such as the labour schemes proposed by Proudhon, Bray and Gray – are replicated today in the many and various reformist options to address monetary challenges.

Typical reforms are monetary alternatives rather than an alternative to money. They vary in how they might be applied. On the one hand, grassroots initiatives include localised (place-limited) currency systems, credit-based LETS (labour exchange trading schemes), and community-oriented banks. On the other hand, more bureaucratic and top-down versions include Odum’s ‘emergy’ equivalent and labour-time equivalence/tickets. All assume that simply replacing the form of equivalence will be constitutive of a better oiled economy.

The strategic importance of provoking all people, not just economists, to think about the role of money within a market economy, and to think about how planning might operate more democratically and deal with the organic essence of our and other beings in terms of values and reproduction, cannot be underestimated. Prefigurative experiments abound at the grass roots as younger generations take the Science and Security Board of the Bulletin for Atomic Scientists Doomsday Clock seriously, set as it is to ‘A moment of historic danger: It is still 90 seconds to midnight’.

Activists engaged in prefiguration in relevant movements either set out knowing or find out along the way all the impracticalities and unsustainabilities of production for trade, of money as a medium of exchange, and propagator of growth dynamics. Examples of such prefigurative experiments include the degrowth formations Cargonomia (Budapest) and Haus des Wandels (peri-urban Berlin) as in Nelson (2024) and exchange-logic-free communities in Germany (Kothari, 2023). Working with real values, seasons, local Earth and people they loosen monetary ties between contributions and output, arranging themselves and their activities on the rational basis of needs at both ends and re Earth.

Set in late capitalism where the ongoing intensification as well as expansion of monetary values and relation continues, many prefigurative activists resist and transform in familiar ways – minimising monetary arrangements, including their own paid work, in favour of arrangements made in real values. Many younger generations of activists are also scholars part-time. They analyse, reflect on and critique their experiences and write up their findings to share. Collectives run on the basis of one purse and/or giving monetary payments on the basis of ability. They rely on voluntary donations, including auctions where collectives proceed in rounds of collections, as in face-to-face crowd funding. They dethrone money.

There is a lot of criticism of these kinds of activities from certain leftist theorists who challenge and deride small scale activities. In working towards a horizontalist endpoint, they do not see that experimenting in concrete ways and scaling out is much more important than designing top down policies and scaling up. Learning and refining so transformative strategies can multiply, prefiguration involves exercising everyday skills of co-governance, of caring and sharing. We need to develop confidence in a range of ways of supporting ourselves sustainably and securely as late capitalist both booms and busts around us. The more that such activities can demonstrate that another world is possible, the more support this line of action will attract.

As we embody our arguments and embolden ourselves, we know that we face the same challenge of all anti-capitalists – to reappropriate our powers to decide how we live. We must create strategies not only to recover control of the means of production but also to heal one another and Earth from the ravages of capitalism. We must occupy and establish money-free commons.

References

Exner, Andreas; Morgan, Justin; Nahrada, Franz; Nelson, Anitra; Siefkes, Christian (2020) ‘Demonetize: The problem is money’ in Burkhart Corinna, Schmelzer, Matthias and Treu, Nina (eds) Degrowth in Movement(s): Exploring Pathways for Transformation. London: Zero Books: 159–70.

Kothari, Ashish (2023) ‘Living beyond capitalism: The commune movement in Germany’, 13 October, Meer (Economy and Politics), accessed 15 March 2024 – https://www.meer.com/en/76457-living-beyond-capitalism

Marx, Karl (1959 [1932]) Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844. Moscow: Progress Publishers as revised and reprinted by the Marxists.org archive, accessed 15 March 2024 – https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1844/manuscripts/preface.htm

Marx, Karl (1993) [1957–1958]) Grundrisse. London: Penguin Books (and New Left Review).

Miéville, China (2023) A Spectre, Haunting: On The Communist Manifesto. [Specifically, Appendix C: Preface to the 1883 German Edition by Karl marx and Frederick Engels (1882).] London: Head of Zeus (Apollo Book)/Bloomsbury Publishing.

Nelson, Anitra (1999/2014) Marx’s Concept of Money: The God of Commodities. Abingdon: Routledge.

Nelson, Anitra (2011) Life Without Money: Building Fair and Sustainable Economies. London: Pluto Press.

Nelson, Anitra (2016) ‘“Your money or your life”: Money and socialist transformation’ Capitalism Nature Socialism 27(4): 40–60.

Nelson, Anitra (2022a) Beyond Money: A Postcapitalist Strategy. London: Pluto Press.

Nelson, Anitra (2022b) Beyond Money: Yenomon. Eight-minute educational video, accessed 15 March 2024 – https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=IOTAvryFjO4 or https://vimeo.com/722765718

Nelson, Anitra (2024, forthcoming May) ‘Pre-figurative Hybrids for Post-carbon Inclusion’, in Horne, Ralph; Ambrose, Aimee; Walker, Gordon and Nelson, Anitra (eds) Post-Carbon Inclusion: Transitions Built on Justice. Bristol: Bristol University Press.

Rubel, Maximilien and Crump, John (1987) Non-Market Socialism in the Nineteenth and Twentieth Century. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

The post Value Par Excellence: Money versus Real Values appeared first on Progress in Political Economy (PPE).

The Wealth of a Nation: Institutional Foundations of English Capitalism – review

Published by Anonymous (not verified) on Mon, 08/04/2024 - 9:17pm in

In The Wealth of a Nation: Institutional Foundations of English CapitalismGeoffrey Hodgson traces the roots of modern capitalism to financial and legal institutions established in England in the 17th and 18th centuries. Hodgson’s astute historical analysis foregrounds the alienability of property rights as a key condition of capitalism’s rise to supremacy, though it leaves questions around the social dimensions of the free market system unanswered, writes S M Amadae.

The Wealth of a Nation: Institutional Foundations of English Capitalism. Geoffrey M. Hodgson. Princeton University Press. 2024.

Book cover of The Wealth of a Nation by Geoffrey Hodgson showing a painting of people, horses and a factory emitting smoke against a sunset sky.English capitalism was built on empire and slavery…State intervention and slavery are examples of impurities within capitalism. Impurities can be necessary or contingent for the system. Some state intervention was arguably necessary, but slavery was not. (13)

Countering conventional understandings of capitalism, Geoffrey Hodgson contends that “Secure property rights were not enough,” because “[m]ore wealth had to become alienable and usable as collateral for borrowing and financing investment” (119). Hodgson’s The Wealth of a Nation: Institutional Foundations of English Capitalism is a welcome contribution to heterodox economics that incorporates historical excavation and theoretical analysis to provide refreshing nuance to established accounts of the rise of capitalism. Hodgson provides historical details of Great Britain’s early modern property rights and finance institutions, building on his previous works and covering a dense corpus of theories and data going back to Adam Smith’s 1776 Wealth of Nations. Hodgson’s analysis of the financial origins of English capitalism focuses on types of property rights from 1689 to 1760 and varieties of financial credit supporting British industrialisation between 1760 and 1830. While readers can expect a perceptive analysis of the origins of British capitalism, they should not expect a critique of the social dimensions of the free market system.

The Wealth of a Nation […] incorporates historical excavation and theoretical analysis to provide refreshing nuance to established accounts of the rise of capitalism.

Part II, “Explaining England’s Economic Development,” including Chapter Three “Land, Law, War,” Chapter Four “From the Glorious to the Industrial Revolution,” and Chapter Five “Finance and Industrialization,” carries the brunt of Hodgson’s argumentation. Three aspects of the book stand out. The first is his overarching argument that the central institution enabling the rise of modern political economy in England was finance: the ability to alienate the ownership of land and other property to serve as collateral for investment loans. The second is Hodgson’s heterodox economic analysis emphasising historical contingency (as opposed to universal laws); Darwinian Variation, Selection, Replication (203-206); and the role of institutions. The third is Hodgson’s apparent embrace of capitalism. He celebrates the productive power of finance capital and industrial investment, but eschews a critical analysis of capitalism’s social consequences articulated by the likes of Karl Marx, John Maynard Keynes and Karl Polanyi.

[Hodgson] celebrates the productive power of finance capital and industrial investment, but eschews a critical analysis of capitalism’s social consequences

Hodgson engages the theories of Karl Marx, Douglass North and Barry Weingast and Deirdre McCloskey, criticising their arguments for being incomplete or flawed. Marx identified the exploitation of the working class by the bourgeoisie; he missed that changes in law preceded changes in the material base that ultimately consolidated bourgeois power. North and Weingast apprehend the importance of secure property rights but missed that these could encompass feudal property rights mandating primogeniture (oldest son inherits all property) and entailments rather than the new class of alienable property rights. McCloskey rightly focuses on ideas as a force for social evolution but misses the exigencies of paying for costly wars and the practical need for legal means to pay off sovereign debt.

The key underlying factor of the British Industrial Revolution from 1760-1830 was the ability to obtain finance.

Hodgson’s treatment is astute. The Dutch were leaders in public finance, and William III’s accession to the British throne in 1689 brought those practices into Britain (121). The period from 1689-1815 was one of “war capitalism” requiring that the state be efficient in raising taxes. The state gained the right to create money by decree, and debt itself could be sold along with contractual obligations to repay the debt. Hodgson dates the financial revolution to 1660-1760 (135) and associates the growing sovereign debt with the need to finance war efforts. The key underlying factor of the British Industrial Revolution from 1760-1830 was the ability to obtain finance. Hodgson challenges the conventional view that entrepreneurs obtained loans from family and friends. His argument rests on documenting that investors were able to stake collateral for their loans. He presents evidence on mortgages, such as for canals, and the rising ratio of capital existing as financial assets versus as physical assets. The British banking system had to adapt to offer credit for investment because the central bank was focused on financing sovereign debt for war efforts.

Hodgson redirects attention from the security of property rights to their alienability as the driving institutional invention critical for capitalism to emerge. Slaves represented a crucial category of this exchangeable type of property. Hodgson acknowledges that “By the end of the eighteenth century, slaves amounted to about a third of the capital value of all owned assets in the British Empire” (109). A sizeable category of alienable property in the early 18th century was that of slaves: £6.4 billion was land, buildings, animals, ships, equipment and other non-human assets, while £3 billion was slaves (2021 currency values, 149). Hodgson’s treatment of slaves’ contribution to the origins of what Adam Smith called the “system of natural liberty” is limited to their functional role as legally institutionalised property that could be alienated. Readers looking to heterodox economics to provide a critical stance on the origins of western free markets may seek more than Hodgson’s proposition that the institution of slavery was merely a contingent factor in the system’s rise. Hodgson acknowledges that the £20 million compensation paid to former slave owners for the 1833 Slavery Abolition Act stands as a historically unprecedented sum of liquid financial capital freely available for industrial investment in the 19th century.

The £20 million compensation paid to former slave owners for the 1833 Slavery Abolition Act stands as a historically unprecedented sum of liquid financial capital freely available for industrial investment in the 19th century.

In a twist of prevailing perception that the burden of debt is a form of bondage (eg David Graeber’s Debt, 2012), Hodgson frames indebtedness as the means of liberation to finance capital, which in turn drives economic growth. Hodson effectively defends Hernando De Soto’s property rights institutions to increase the welfare of the destitute by issuing land titles as a means to obtain credit. In a similar inversion of conventional sentiment, we can recall Adam Smith’s admonishment, counter to contemporary American libertarians, that tax, including poll tax, “is to the person who pays it a badge, not of slavery, but of liberty” because tax payers are subjects of government.

Hodgson adopts a Darwinian-inspired methodology based on variation, selection, and replication (the “V-S-R” system, 204).  The section “Applying Darwinism to Scientific and Economic Evolution,” (206) is conjectural. He observes that, “Some individuals were more successful than others, affecting their chances of survival and procreation” (207). He rejects either a material account or a mental account of agency. The latter refers to “folk psychology” which attributes action to individuals’ desires and beliefs. Hodgson follows the school of thought holding that human action occurs before intention is conscious or rationalised (189-190). He holds that habits and dispositions, rather than deliberately formed intentions, govern action and form the bedrock of institutions.

[Hodgson] holds that habits and dispositions, rather than deliberately formed intentions, govern action and form the bedrock of institutions.

How, then, do we assess the merits of, or the underlying affirming conditions for, either the institution of slavery or alienable property and financial capital? Hodgson observes that,

People often obey laws out of respect for authority and justice, and not because they calculate advantages and disadvantages of compliance. Dispositions to respect authority have evolved over millions of years because they aided cohesion and survival of primate and human groups (201).

Hodgson’s argument that alienable property and appropriate financial institutions for investment were a condition for the rise of capitalism in Britain is convincing. However, without a clear conceptualisation of effective human agency, other than that driven by dispositions and habits, we are left with the stubborn question of the extent to which capitalist institutions are either emancipatory or the best means to better the human condition.

Note: This post gives the views of the author, and not the position of the LSE Review of Books blog, or of the London School of Economics and Political Science.

Image: The painting Coalbrookdale by Night by Philippe Jacques de Loutherbourg depicting the Bedlam furnaces at Coalbrookdale in Shropshire, England. Credit: The Science Museum, London.

Book Release: “Anxiety: A Philosophical Guide”

Published by Anonymous (not verified) on Fri, 29/03/2024 - 11:04pm in

I’m pleased to make note here of the release, on March 19th, of my book Anxiety: A Philosophical Guide published by Princeton University Press. Here is the book’s description and cover:

  • Today, anxiety is usually thought of as a pathology, the most diagnosed and medicated of all psychological disorders. But anxiety isn’t always or only a medical condition. Indeed, many philosophers argue that anxiety is a normal, even essential, part of being human, and that coming to terms with this fact is potentially transformative, allowing us to live more meaningful lives by giving us a richer understanding of ourselves. In Anxiety, Samir Chopra explores valuable insights about anxiety offered by ancient and modern philosophies—Buddhism, existentialism, psychoanalysis, and critical theory. Blending memoir and philosophy, he also tells how serious anxiety has affected his own life—and how philosophy has helped him cope with it.
  • Chopra shows that many philosophers—including the Buddha, Kierkegaard, Nietzsche, Freud, and Heidegger—have viewed anxiety as an inevitable human response to existence: to be is to be anxious. Drawing on Karl Marx and Herbert Marcuse, Chopra examines how poverty and other material conditions can make anxiety worse, but he emphasizes that not even the rich can escape it. Nor can the medicated. Inseparable from the human condition, anxiety is indispensable for grasping it. Philosophy may not be able to cure anxiety but, by leading us to greater self-knowledge and self-acceptance, it may be able to make us less anxious about being anxious.
  • Personal, poignant, and hopeful, Anxiety is a book for anyone who is curious about rethinking anxiety and learning why it might be a source not only of suffering but of insight.

Hijacked: How Neoliberalism Turned The Work Ethic Against Workers and How Workers Can Take It Back – review 

In Hijacked: How Neoliberalism Turned The Work Ethic Against Workers and How Workers Can Take It BackElizabeth Anderson argues that neoliberalism has perverted the Protestant work ethic to exploit workers and enrich the one per cent. Magdalene D’Silva finds the book a compelling call to renew a progressive, socially democratic work ethic that promotes dignity for workers.

Hijacked: How Neoliberalism Turned The Work Ethic Against Workers and How Workers Can Take It Back. Elizabeth Anderson. Cambridge University Press. 2023.

Find this book: amazon-logo

pink and yellow cover of the book Hijacked by Elizabeth AndersonElizabeth Anderson’s excellent 2023 book Hijacked was published the same month Australian multi-millionaire Tim Gurner said:

“Unemployment has to jump … we need to see pain … Employees feel the employer is extremely lucky to have them … We’ve gotta kill that attitude…”

America’s Senator Bernie Sanders rebuked Gurner’s diatribe as “disgusting. It’s hard to believe that you have that kind of mentality among the ruling class in the year 2023.”

Ironically, Gurner’s comments favouring employees’ objectification and employer coercive control show just what Hijacked says is: [T]he ascendance of the conservative work ethic… (which) tells workers … they owe their employers relentless toil and unquestioning obedience under whatever harsh conditions their employer chooses …”(xii).

Indeed, “neoliberalism is the descendant of this harsh version of the work ethic … [i]t entrenches the commodification of labor … people have no alternative but to submit to the arbitrary government of employers to survive.” (xii).

Anderson defines neoliberalism as an ideology favouring market orderings over state regulation […] to maximise the wealth and power of capital relative to labour

Anderson defines neoliberalism as an ideology favouring market orderings over state regulation (xii) to maximise the wealth and power of capital relative to labour (272) where the so-called “de-regulation” of labour and other markets doesn’t liberate ordinary people from the state; it transfers state regulatory authority to the most powerful, dominant firms in each market (xii).

Hijacked follows Anderson’s prior writing on neoliberalism’s replacement of democratically elected public government by the state, with unelected private government by employers. Like other work ethic critiques, Hijacked explains how Puritan theologians behind the work ethic dismissed feelings with contempt for emotional styles of faith worship (3).

Hijacked explains how Puritan theologians behind the work ethic dismissed feelings with contempt for emotional styles of faith worship

The original work ethic proselytised utilitarianism (19) but with inherent contradictions between progressive and conservative ideals (14). Early conservative work ethic advocates included Joseph Priestley, Jeremy Bentham, Thomas Malthus and Edmund Burke (Chapters 2 and 3) who aligned with the new capitalist, manager entrepreneur classes and “lazy landlords, speculators and predatory capitalists” (65) who claimed they exemplified the work ethic (127).

The work ethic split into conservative and progressive versions which Anderson distinguishes by class-based power relations, rather than competitive markets

The work ethic split into conservative and progressive versions which Anderson distinguishes by class-based power relations, rather than competitive markets, as conservatives “favour government by and for property owners, assign different duties to employers and employees, rich and poor” (while expecting) “workers to submit to despotic employer authority” (and) “regard poverty as a sign of bad character … poor workers as morally inferior” (xv).

Progressives like Adam Smith (130-135) supported “democracy and worker self-government. They oppose class-based duties … and reject stigmatization of poverty” (xvi). Anderson traces this “progressive” work ethic to classical liberals like John Locke (Chapter 2), Adam Smith (132-135), John Stuart Mill (Chapter 6) and progressive, socialist thinkers like Karl Marx (Chapter 7) who stressed how paid work should not alienate workers “from their essence or species-being…” (209) but express their individuality, as “[t]he distinctively human essence is to freely shape oneself…” (209).

Marx applied Mill’s emphasis on the importance of individuality, which Anderson links to the Puritan idea that our vocation must match our individual talents and interests (206) whatever our economic class.

Furthermore, Locke “condemned the idle predatory rich as well as able-bodied beggars” (65). Marx applied Mill’s emphasis on the importance of individuality, which Anderson links to the Puritan idea that our vocation must match our individual talents and interests (206) whatever our economic class.

Yet our worthiness now had to be proved (to God) by ‘work’ that entailed: disciplining drudgery (9), slavery (10, 259), racism (97-99), exploitative maltreatment of poor people (106) and industrious productivity (52) which became conspicuously competitive, luxury consumption (170).

Conservatives (Chapters 3, 4) secularised these ideas so the “upper-class targets of the Puritan critique hijacked the work ethic … into an instrument of class warfare against workers. Now only workers were held to its demands … the busy schemers who … extract value from others cast themselves as heroes of the work ethic, the poor as the only scoundrels” (65).

Anderson doesn’t idolise Locke, Smith, J. S. Mill and other early progressive work ethic advocates like Ricardo (Chapter 5) by highlighting harsh contradictions in their views. For example, within Locke’s pro-worker agenda were draconian measures for poor children (61) such that Anderson says Locke’s harsh policies for those he called the idle poor, contain “the seeds of the ultimate hijacking of the work ethic by capital owners” (25).

[Anderson’s] scrutiny of both left and right-wing support of the neoliberal conservative work ethic complements other critiques of the left-wing origins of neoliberal markets.

Anderson criticises the perversion and reversal of the work ethic’s originally progressive, classical liberal aspirations “and successor traditions on the left” (xviii). Her scrutiny of both left and right-wing support of the neoliberal conservative work ethic complements other critiques of the left-wing origins of neoliberal markets. Anderson also says the conservative work ethic arose in a period of rapidly rising productivity and stagnant wages, “when market discipline was reserved for workers, not the rich” (108).

Yet it was the progressive work ethic that culminated in social democracy throughout Western Europe by promoting the “freedom, dignity and welfare of each” (242). Marx was so influenced by the progressive work ethic espoused by classical liberals, his most developed work on economic theory apparently quotes Adam Smith copiously and admiringly (226). Anderson thus contends that criticism of social democracy as a radical break from classical liberalism – is a myth, as ideas like social insurance “developed within the classical liberal tradition” (227).

However, “Cold War ideology represented social democracy as … a slippery slope to totalitarianism … the title of Friederich Hayek’s … Road to Serfdom, says it all” (226).

Social democracy declined worldwide in the 1970s and 1980s when neoliberalism arose and the conservative work ethic returned with the elections of Ronald Reagan and Margaret Thatcher

Social democracy declined worldwide in the 1970s and 1980s when neoliberalism arose and the conservative work ethic returned with the elections of Ronald Reagan and Margaret Thatcher (Chapter 9). Social democratic centre-left parties like the US Democrats and the UK’s Labour Party (293) didn’t counter neoliberalism’s conservative work ethic, as “the demographics of these parties shifted… from the working class to the professional managerial class” (257), seduced by meritocracy ideology in a competitive race for (their own) superior status (257). Anderson’s observation complements Elizabeth Humphry’s research on how Australia’s Labor Party and labour union movement introduced vanguard neoliberalism to Australia against workers, in the 1980s.

[Anderson] argues the focus on efficiency and aggregate growth neglected workers’ conditions and plight as neoliberal work (for welfare) policies degrade people’s autonomy and capabilities

Anderson recognises the success of some neoliberal policies in the US’s economic stagnation in the 1970s, like trucking deregulation, emissions reduction trade schemes and international trade liberalisation (285-287). However, she argues the focus on efficiency and aggregate growth neglected workers’ conditions and plight as neoliberal work (for welfare) policies degrade people’s autonomy and capabilities because “the most important product of our economic system is ourselves” (288).

Hijacked’s last chapter recommends social democracy renewal and updating the progressive work ethic “to ensure … every person … has the resources and opportunities to develop … their talents …  engage with others on terms of trust, sympathy and genuine cooperation” (298). Employees could be empowered through worker cooperatives (297).

A gap in Hijacked’s analysis is a lack of clear definition of “work.” Anderson doesn’t  distinguish between “employment” in a “job,” and rich elites’ voluntary, symbolic “duties,” like those of Britain’s “working royals” who call their activities “work”.

Another dilemma is whether economic class power struggles can change peacefully, noting Peter Turchin says we’re facing ‘end times’ of war and political disintegration because competing elites won’t relinquish power.

Nevertheless, Hijacked is compelling reading for everyone on the left and the right who needs employment in a paid job to survive, so today’s neoliberal conservative work ethic no longer gaslights us to believe our dignity demands our exploitation.

This post gives the views of the author, and not the position of the LSE Review of Books blog, or of the London School of Economics and Political Science. The LSE RB blog may receive a small commission if you choose to make a purchase through the above Amazon affiliate link. This is entirely independent of the coverage of the book on LSE Review of Books.

Image Credit: Daniel Foster on Flickr.

Karl Marx, Class Struggles in France and the historical materialist method!

Published by Anonymous (not verified) on Tue, 29/03/2016 - 6:00am in

Tags 

Karl Marx

Karl Marx did not only involve himself in abstract conceptual work on how to understand the capitalist social relations of production. He was also an engaged analyst of class struggles at his time. This included three separate writings on developments in France: The Class Struggles in France, 1848-1850 (1850); The Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte (1852); and The Civil War in France (1871). In this post, I will discuss key aspects of Marx’s historical materialist approach in relation to The Class Struggles in France, 1848-50 and conclude with some ideas of what this method implies for efforts today to understand the global political economy as well as the possibilities for revolutionary change.

Key aspects of Marx’s method include (1) a focus on the social relations of production, (2) an acknowledgement of different class fractions, (3) the importance of the international dimension in understanding class struggle, as well as (4) the historical specificity of developments in individual countries.

Focus on the social relations of production

For Marx, a focus on the social relations of production is essential, when analysing historical developments and class struggle. He asserts that ‘wage labour is the existing bourgeois organisation of labour. Without it there is no capital, no bourgeoisie, no bourgeois society’. Equally, when examining the reason for the eventual defeat of workers in France in the period of 1848 to 1850, he refers to the social relations surrounding production. ‘What succumbed in these defeats was not the revolution. It was the pre-revolutionary traditional appendages, results of social relationships, which had not yet come to the point of sharp class antagonism’. It is on the basis of how production is organised that he identifies a range of different relevant classes and class fractions in the French struggles from 1948 to 1950.

Different class fractions

Marx assumed that ultimately all capitalist societies would be divided into two large classes, capital and labour. However, he was sensitive to the fact that the development towards this situation was a historical process, within which many more classes and class fractions were involved. In other words, rather than simply thinking in terms of capital and labour, he identified a range of relevant classes on the basis of an analysis of the social relations of production. In France in 1848, this included the industrial proletariat, the petty bourgeoisie such as small shop keepers, the peasant class as well as capital. The latter were sub-divided into different class fractions. ‘The bourgeois class fell apart into two big fractions, which, alternately, the big landed proprietors under the restored monarchy and the finance aristocracy and the industrial bourgeoisie under the July monarchy, had maintained a monopoly of order’. He further established that finance capital was dominant in France, while manufacturing played a subordinate role. In short, Marx was prepared to modify and adjust his general concepts such as capital and labour to the concrete empirical situation he was investigating.

The international dimension

Marx always understood capitalism as an international phenomenon and appreciated that class struggles within one country were directly affected by economic developments elsewhere. In 1848 he wrote that ‘French production relations are conditioned by the foreign trade of France, by her position on the world market and the laws thereof; how should France break them without a European revolutionary war, which would strike back at the despot of the world market, England?’. And equally, when discussing why there had been a revolution in France in February 1848, he pointed out that ‘the second great economic event which hastened the outbreak of the revolution, was a general commercial and industrial crisis in England’. The capitalist social relations of production and class struggle can only be understood within an international context.

The historical specificity

When analysing concrete struggles, Marx was careful not to generalise his findings from one country to another. In the case of France, he acknowledged the rather different production structure from the one in England, which then, in turn, led to a different assessment. Discussing the position of French manufacturing, he stated that ‘in England industry rules; in France, agriculture. In England industry requires free trade; in France, protection, national monopoly besides other monopolies. French industry does not dominate production; the French industrialists, therefore, do not dominate the French bourgeoisie. This focus on historical specificity already included an implicit reference to uneven development, the fact that different countries are in rather different positions within the global economy, which was later developed by Leon Trotsky in the notion of ‘uneven and combined development’. ‘Just as the period of crisis occurs later on the Continent than in England, so does that of prosperity. The original process always takes place in England; she is the demiurge of the bourgeois cosmos. On the Continent, the different phases of the cycle through which bourgeois society is ever speeding anew, occur in secondary and tertiary form’. This historically different location has then also implications for where revolutionary uprisings are more likely to erupt. ‘Violent outbreaks’, Marx argues, ‘must naturally occur earlier in the extremities of the bourgeois body than in its heart, since here the possibility of adjustment is greater than there’ (see also Uneven and combined development and the issue of resistance in the UK!).

Karl Marx and the analysis of the global economic crisis

In his assessment of class struggles in France from 1848 to 1850, Marx highlighted the importance of crisis as an opportunity for revolutionary change. ‘A new revolution is only possible in consequence of a new crisis. It is, however, also just as certain as this’. Today, we face another, much larger economic crisis on a global, but especially also European scale. Marx’s method developed more than 100 years ago remains relevant. First, we cannot understand the crisis by looking solely at issues such as the regulation of financial markets, as vulgar economists do. Rather, we need to analyse the underlying social relations of production and the related developments, which have brought this crisis about. Second, we need to identify the different social class forces, when thinking about agency for change. We cannot automatically assume, for example, that all workers are likely to be revolutionary agents. Different class fractions of labour are likely to act differently. Third, the international dimension is of importance. As different countries are in a different location in the global economy, so are different labour movements. It is no surprise that Greek workers are much more involved in open resistance, being in the periphery of the European political economy, than British workers from the core. Finally, we need to investigate the historical specificity of the capitalist social relations of production and here the way capitalism has evolved since the mid-19th century. While Marx’s method can be used for an analysis today, his findings cannot simply be transferred.

This post was originally posted on Trade Unions and Global Restructuring (5 July 2012) and appears here as one of the texts originally read in the Marxism Reading Group. 

Karl Marx and the Dictatorship of the Proletariat

Published by Anonymous (not verified) on Sat, 19/03/2016 - 7:35am in

HollowayThe notion of the ‘dictatorship of the proletariat’ is widely vilified. Often linked to Stalin’s authoritarian rule in the Soviet Union, there is little positive said about it. Moreover, the negative evaluation is also regularly linked back to Lenin and his idea of a vanguard party taking over state power in order to change society for the better. As John Holloway argues in Change the World Without Taking Power, ‘you cannot build a society of non-power relations by conquering power. Once the logic of power is adopted, the struggle against power is already lost’. And yet, these reflections overlook Marx’s own discussion of what the dictatorship of the proletariat may entail in practice. Most importantly they neglect his analysis of the Paris Commune in The Civil War in France (1871). For as Engels pointed out in 1891, ‘well and good, gentlemen, do you want to know what this dictatorship looks like? Look at the Paris Commune. That was the Dictatorship of the Proletariat’.

In this post, I will look more closely at Marx’s discussion of the Paris Commune and his ideas about how to organise popular government.

It is especially the third part of the Third Address, given by Marx to the General Council of the International Workingmen’s Association in May 1871, which is relevant for our purpose here. First, Marx makes clear that the proletariat cannot simply take over the bourgeois state and its institutions, if it wants to change society. ‘The working class cannot simply lay hold of the ready-made state machinery, and wield it for its own purposes’. Parallel to the ‘pace at which the progress of modern industry developed, widened, intensified the class antagonism between capital and labour, the state power assumed more and more the character of the national power of capital over labour, of a public force organised for social enslavement, of an engine of class despotism’. In order to bring about a new society, therefore, the very institutions of the bourgeois state form have to be changed first. For example, ‘the police was at once stripped of its political attributes’ in the Paris Commune. Furthermore, Marx recognised the importance of education for a truly free society and praised the Commune’s steps in this area. ‘The whole of the educational institutions were opened to the people gratuitously, and at the same time cleared of all interference of church and state’.

Second, Marx highlights the governance structure, introduced by the Paris Commune. ‘The Commune was formed of the municipal councillors, chosen by universal suffrage in the various wards of the town, responsible and revocable at short terms’. In other words, rather than representing authoritarian government, ‘the dictatorship of the proletariat’ is a fundamentally democratic set-up, within which the individual has a direct impact on decision-making in that delegates have the task to transfer local decisions and can be re-called and replaced at any time. Equally, in relation to the judiciary, ‘like the rest of public servants, magistrates and judges were to be elective, responsible, and revocable’. The overall goal is the ‘self-government of the producers’. This system, once established in Paris, should then also be implemented in the rural communities, with delegates being elected to represent these districts to the National Delegation in Paris. Again, each delegate was ‘to be at any time revocable and bound by the mandate imperative (formal instructions) of his constituents’. In short, for Marx the dictatorship of the proletariat always implied direct participation by the people in all aspects of the decision-making process. It did not mean authoritarian rule.

Importantly, restructuring of the bourgeois state form did not simply focus on bourgeois institutions. For Marx, it was always clear that capitalist exploitation was rooted in the way production was organised around wage labour and the private ownership of the means of production. To overcome exploitation, therefore, it was necessary to abolish private property and this is precisely what the Paris Commune did. ‘Yes, gentlemen, the Commune intended to abolish that class property which makes the labour of the many the wealth of the few. It aimed at the expropriation of the expropriators. It wanted to make individual property a truth by transforming the means of production, land, and capital, now chiefly the means of enslaving and exploiting labour, into mere instruments of free and associated labor’. In other words, the economy cannot be regarded as separate from politics, if true change is to be accomplished.

Finally, Marx was aware of the importance of the Commune’s international dimension. ‘If the Commune was thus the true representative of all the healthy elements of French society, and therefore the truly national government, it was, at the same time, as a working men’s government, as the bold champion of the emancipation of labour, emphatically international’. Thus, for Marx it was always clear that the defeat of capitalism could not only be achieved in one country or even one city – after all the Paris Commune fell after a couple of months – but must always have an international aspiration.

To establish ‘the dictatorship of the proletariat’ as experimented by the Paris Commune is not really on today’s agenda. And yet, perhaps developments in Venezuela are potentially one step into this direction? The so-called Housing Mission, for example, did not only succeed in building thousands of homes for the poor, but also managed to include barrio residents in their planning and construction, as argued by Steve Ellner in 2012. To conclude, the dictatorship of the proletariat, as envisaged by the Paris Commune, is an aspiration at best at this point in time, but an aspiration worthwhile to pursue and push further.

This post originally appeared on Trade Unions and Global Restructuring (14 September 2012) and appears here as one of the texts originally read in the Marxism Reading Group.